Most academic philosophers live in a world of
pharmaceutical paternalism: new treatments are subject to premarket approval by
State regulatory agencies, and patients will only be able to access them
through medical prescription. Outside academic philosophy, there has been a
long tradition of pharmaceutical libertarianism, advocating for allowing
patients to take their risks with experimental treatments without State or
medical interference. Precisely because this tradition has had almost no philosophical
echo, Jessica Flanigan’s Pharmaceutical Freedom
was a necessary book. Its broad claims and intuitions are not new. The real
originality lies in the thorough examination and defence of the right to
self-medicate from the standpoint of contemporary moral philosophy.
Flanigan grounds her arguments on the patient’s
authority in knowing what will promote her overall well-being and in deciding
what to do, with an original twist: she shows that supporters of informed
consent should also endorse self-medication, as it is based on the same
foundations. She criticizes regulatory paternalism for failing to adequately
protect public health: informed self-medication could do better. Moreover,
pharmaceutical regulators “wrongfully kill patients by withholding access to
investigational drugs”, until they are approved. Drug prescription is equally
objectionable for restricting the right to die, the right to use recreational
drugs, the right to self-enhancement and the right to use pharmaceuticals for
non-medical reasons. Flanigan defends that patients should “develop drugs
outside the formal mechanisms of the approval process, disobey pharmaceutical
regulations, and protest existing policies” (p. 165), even if they do not have
the support of a majority of voters (“biased against rights of
self-medication”). If, at this point, you are wondering whether pharmaceutical
companies do have any particular moral obligation towards patients, Flanigan
defends that it is an industry like any other: there is no reason to expect
that they provide affordable products. Pharmaceutical marketing (e.g., direct
to consumer advertising) should be deregulated, such as any other instance of
paternalistic health regulation. Tort law provides enough defence for
pharmaceutical consumers to stand against any industry misdeed.
These are the claims that Flanigan makes in her
book, and I think the author deserves all the praise to make them as boldly and
straightforwardly as possible. Most of these claims, although with different
justifications, have been around since the passage of the 1962 Food and Drug
Administration Act. It established a pre-market approval system for drugs on
the basis of the safety and efficacy they showed in randomized clinical trials.
Flanigan surely draws on these libertarian/pro-industry sources (e.g., W.
Wardell and L. Lasagna are cited; T. Stossel is mentioned in the
acknowledgements), but she constructs arguments that rely, to an unprecedented
scale, on principled philosophical considerations (after the steps of Allen
Buchanan, Robert Veatch, etc.). Nonetheless, Flanigan has also a policy
proposal: a supervision system for pharmaceutical markets. Instead of pure
market control (customers select the good treatments buying them), in the best
libertarian tradition, or ex post
withdrawal of the dangerous compounds (Wardell and Lasagna’s approach),
Flanigan defends a certification system,
in which a public agency tests the treatments already sold in the market and
assesses their safety without gatekeeping powers.
I leave to moral philosophers the discussion of
her more principled arguments and, as a philosopher of science, let me take
issue instead with this latest proposal. My general contention is that Flanigan
tends to overstate her moral claims at the expenses of every other
consideration. A case in point is precisely the certification of drug safety. For Flanigan,
“Drug safety is a normative judgment that requires knowledge about how
the risks and side effects of a drug fit into a patient’s life as a whole”
(p.10). The 1962 FDA Act definition of safety linked it to efficacy as shown in
one particular experimental design: randomized clinical trials should establish
whether a treatment for a given condition would reliably have certain effects.
This is the positive concept of safety: the choice of a treatment outcome might
be normative, but regulators care about it being predictable. Flanigan claims
there is something more to safety: a drug may be unsafe for the FDA (e.g., having
known adverse effects) and yet a patient may think it is safe for her to take
it and, according to Flanigan, she should have the last word about it. Flanigan provides three arguments about why
people can consent to drugs that carry known (and unknown) risks (p.24),
showing how consent to risky alternatives (rejecting treatments, participation
in phase I trials) is considered acceptable, and yet it seems unjustified to
consent to risk thresholds below FDA-safety. So why not leave the ultimate
assessment of safety up to the patients?
This is Flanigan’s certification proposal: let
regulatory agencies certify the predictable risks of a treatment and leave to
patients the informed decision to take them. On purely normative grounds, I
think this is a very persuasive idea for anyone with even a minimal
anti-paternalist inclination. The problem is, of course, the positive
implementation, about which Flanigan provides almost no detail. Her intuition
is that for the majority of patients who value their health, not much would
change: they will rely on certification, while the most desperate/daring
patients will trust their own judgment (p. 62). But I disagree here: the devil
is in the details. Randomized clinical trials are long and complicated
experiments, often involving thousands of patients, and completing them usually
takes years. Assuming that Flanigan’s system adopts the current evidential
yardstick, certification will be equally slow. There will be many non-certified
systems in the market for which patients will only have the non-certified
information provided by the manufacturer. Patients in need of these treatments
will have to trust the honesty of the manufacturing company in reporting risks
(p.26), and litigate if, after trying the drug, she feels cheated: according to
Flanigan, tort law provides a better protection for her rights than any
pharmaceutical regulator (p. 221).
I doubt it. For a start, there is an extensive
academic literature on the misdeeds of pharmaceutical marketing that should
give us some pause about its honesty. This literature is simply absent from the
two sections in which Flanigan discusses the topic (pp. 209-217). Instead,
pro-industry views are presented on a positive note, giving them, I fear, more epistemic
weight than they deserve. E.g., I was intrigued by an unusual reference on the
positive effects of direct-to-consumer advertising (p. 211, footnote 13) for
which just the title was given and a long Proquest link. Searching on Proquest,
I found that the paper was published in the “Web Exclusives” supplement of a
journal, with some very serious scholars as lead authors and some co-authors
from a marketing agency. After reading Sergio Sismondo’s work on pharmaceutical
publication planning, I would have expected Flanigan to add some caveats on the
reliability of such a source (and contrast it with more standard sources on the
topic).
But even if the libertarian pharmaceutical
consumer cannot trust the manufacturer, if she feels cheated after receiving
the non-certified treatment, she can always sue for dishonest reporting about
risk. My question is: on what grounds can she contest the honesty of the
non-certified brochure? On the one hand, there are many evidential standards
that can be used to argue that a drug is safe/effective, ranging from clinical
trials with different designs to observational studies or simple expert
judgment. If the industry is self-serving in choosing the evidence reported in
the brochure, how can a court adjudicate whether the information was accurate? On
the other hand, given that testing treatments involve long and expensive
studies, how can the dissatisfied libertarian patient ground her legal claims?
Judges and patients may both defer, of course, on the certification agency test
as a benchmark, but then we would be almost back at the status quo: which
company will dare to launch a product without conducting long clinical trials,
for fear of litigation?
This are not mere counterfactual scenarios:
this is the history of pharmaceutical markets. For example, legitimate British manufacturers
in the 1930s were demanding a regulatory intervention in order to protect
themselves against the rogue competitors who sold fake drugs based on pretence
tests, undermining their own sales. Fraud prosecution offered little protection
(against Flanigan’s optimism), because it was difficult to prove fraud in court
without an evidential benchmark for authenticity. Again, I cannot help feeling
that Flanigan cherry-picks the evidence that supports her case. She cites
uncritically the usual bunch of old econometric studies that provide ammunition
against our current regulatory system (Peltzman, Temin, etc). Yet, the key
concept of Dan Carpenter’s landmark monograph on the FDA, a thick volume of
analytical social science published less than a decade ago, is dispatched in
just one sentence (p.127).
Summing up, there is a significant gap to bridge between Flanigan’s normative understanding of drug safety and the practical implementation of a certification system for “positive” safety. Flanigan is at her best in the discussion of moral principles (which is 2/3 of her book), but really does a poor job when it comes to policy recommendations (the reminding 1/3). I have been clearly unfair to her work in focusing on this latter aspect, but, I think, it is for a good reason. If I were a libertarian patient willing to dismantle the FDA, I would want some reassurance that we won’t see a regression to the world of unpunished pharmaceutical frauds of the early twentieth century. Moral argument, in other words, is not enough for policy action. But we should be grateful to Flanigan for articulating the libertarian case so well and making it part of our philosophical conversation on the pharmaceutical world.
{March, 2018}
No hay comentarios:
Publicar un comentario